PDF Wittgenstein on Thought and Will (Wittgensteins Thought and Legacy)

Free download. Book file PDF easily for everyone and every device. You can download and read online Wittgenstein on Thought and Will (Wittgensteins Thought and Legacy) file PDF Book only if you are registered here. And also you can download or read online all Book PDF file that related with Wittgenstein on Thought and Will (Wittgensteins Thought and Legacy) book. Happy reading Wittgenstein on Thought and Will (Wittgensteins Thought and Legacy) Bookeveryone. Download file Free Book PDF Wittgenstein on Thought and Will (Wittgensteins Thought and Legacy) at Complete PDF Library. This Book have some digital formats such us :paperbook, ebook, kindle, epub, fb2 and another formats. Here is The CompletePDF Book Library. It's free to register here to get Book file PDF Wittgenstein on Thought and Will (Wittgensteins Thought and Legacy) Pocket Guide.

If people were used to seeing nothing but green squares and red circles, they might regard a green circle with the same kind of mistrust with which they would regard a freak, and, for example, they might even say it is really a red circle, but has something of a If we only saw one of our primary colours, red say, extremely seldom and only in tiny expanses, if we could not prepare colours for painting, if red occurred only in particular connections with other colours, say only at the very tips of leaves of certain trees, these tips gradually changing from green to red in the autumn, then nothing would be more natural than to call red a degenerate green.

Undoubtedly Wittgenstein also wants to comment on the peculiar role of thought experiments in philosophical language-games. In order to explain the importance of a philosophical insight we don't have to find new facts; we have to remind philosophers of facts that are so general that they are hardly ever mentioned. These facts belong to what G. But seeing this as problematic or scandalous is an inexhaustible source of problems:.

In the light Wittgenstein can be seen as a kind of high priest of contingency. It has even been suggested that what we must pass over in the Tractatus is the causal law, and that the silence should come from our being awestruck by it Cudahy — But even if this wasn't true, and it isn't, it seems that Wittgenstein sees living in the Humean world of unpredictability as a kind of leap of faith that he recommends equally to logical positivists and Moorean common-sense philosophers Marcotte 64—66; Churchill 63— And perhaps even Heideggerian fear-of-loss-of-being can be treated using this form of alienation as a philosophical therapy Cooper — In his last notes from the years —51 Wittgenstein examines Moore's defence of common sense, colour concepts, and concepts in the philosophy of mind, wishing to clarify the peculiar role certain experiential propositions have in our normal world-picture.

Although these propositions are a posteriori , their truth belongs to our system of reference so axiomatically that they do not differ in practice from a priori propositions. These kinds of recondite and radical deviations from our world-picture, such as rejecting the causal law, are hard to tell apart from madness. Or what is the difference between my treating it as a mistake and my treating it as a mental disturbance? Like magic realists in literature, Wittgenstein tries to convey the heuristic value of horrifying and sinister phenomena: to light a non-evaluative interest in events that are unpleasant as they are.

The isolation of new distinctions from our "familiar," "ordinary" language is something uncanny Cavell 94—98; cf. Zekauskas — Wittgenstein snaps his little pictures of reality precisely through the cracks that open up between analytic philosophy and everyday experience. Part of his originality is that he asks the skeptic to define what the skeptic wishes to deny Cavell The strangeness of skepticism is then evident to the skeptic, because he managed to define what he thought undefinable.

Wittgenstein's thought experiments are planned to be unconvincing Barnett 49— In the horror caused by philosophizing the most notable thing is its festive nature, which is connected with seeing philosophy as a kind of pious sacrament Rhees Even though he doesn't often use this concept, it is a certain lack of piety which Wittgenstein considers to be the cause of unhealthy philosophizing.

However, piety has fallen out of fashion as a measure of a philosopher's success. This has happened not only because it arouses the wrong kind of religious associations as a concept, but also because it can appear equally strongly in conjunction with several competing philosophical stances Abrams —; Phillips Anthony Holiday — has noted that when Wittgenstein defends supposedly primitive folkways from Frazer's critique, he uses methods which can also be used to defend the healthy Western understanding from the aberrations of Western philosophy.

Wittgensteinian philosophy is a ritual, but it does not fight against any mythical evil spirits; actually it fights attitudes to life, like those of the Vienna Circle, which reject rituals and piety. Science, which sees no reason to believe in God, wants to deprive Wittgenstein of experiences that made the people of the past — but not Wittgenstein — believe in God Phillips —; Lurie — Wittgenstein's Nietzschean, agonal atheism, which thinks that the non-existence of God is no laughing matter quite the contrary , is much more horrifying to a scientific atheist than any theistic world religions Clack b: ; cf.

Churchill In fact these world religions are often allied with scientific atheists in condemning piety directed towards atheism! As for philosophers, they do not fight so much against Wittgenstein's own expressions of piety as for their own limitations concerning piety Hertzberg ; Sachs According to Wittgenstein, the expressions of piety have generally degenerated and cheapened in modern culture Bouwsma 33— It is too easy to pretend that one is following them for them to reveal their true background of tremendous spiritual forces.

Supposing you meet someone in the street and he tells you he has lost his greatest friend, in a voice extremely expressive of his emotion. You might say: "It was extraordinarily beautiful, the way he expressed himself. Rush Rhees — has noted that the incompetence of philosophers does not have consequences as dramatic or spectacular as the incompetence of engineers or carpenters, and that this is a reason why the incompetence of philosophers is frequently hidden. In fact there is no unanimosity about suitable criteria for success in philosophy, since such criteria are always bound together with a certain metaphilosophical vision.

In this context Wittgenstein's unexpectability is a test of his own vision, one he applies both to himself, his pupils and the objects of his criticism. Robert Oppenheimer once famously said that developing the atomic bomb had taught nuclear physicists to know sin, "in some sort of crude sense, which no vulgarity, no humor, no overstatement can quite extinguish". In the same way, in the same sense, Wittgenstein wanted to bring sin into the consciousness of philosophers; to make philosophy "something deeper and less harmless" Wittgenstein a: It seems that Wittgenstein agrees with Bataille's opinion as regards the exceptional philosophical cogency which there is in the primitive and aconceptual "inner experience":.

In the English-speaking world Stanley Cavell, one of Conant's heroes and mine, has for four decades been a central developer of a Wittgensteinian interpretation in which the literary and philosophical aspects are inseparable. In his early essays "The Availability of Wittgenstein's Philosophy" Cavell and "Existentialism and Analytical Philosophy" Cavell he created an idea later developed at considerable length in his main work, The Claim of Reason Cavell : the philosophy of Wittgenstein — which for Cavell means exclusively the philosophy of the Philosophical Investigations — can best be interpreted as confessional literature comparable with the works of such religious writers as St.

Augustine and Kierkegaard. These Christians struggled against ordinary sins, but Wittgenstein is bothered by the sin of philosophizing. In the dialogues of the Investigations the philosopher Wittgenstein tries to seduce the anti-philosophical therapist Wittgenstein, and the book documents the latter's struggles against the former Cavell 91— Kierkegaard's theologians, who prevent authentic existence, are replaced with Wittgenstein's philosophers, who seek to prevent the authentic use of ordinary language Cavell This resembles the secularization of confessional tradition in German Romanticism Rowe In addition Cavell often compares Wittgenstein's homages to ordinariness and spontaneousness with the American "homeliness" of Emerson and Thoreau.

This is the second main source of his own "homegrown" philosophy. An important sub-plot in Cavell's philosophy is the strangeness of everyday life from a philosophical point of view — the "uncanniness of the ordinary," to quote the title of one of his essays Cavell This has led other Wittgenstein scholars to suggest that a key form of Wittgensteinian therapy is to "quicken the sense of the queer," as O. Bouwsma put it in his essay on the Blue Book , which along with Cavell's early papers was an important early attempt to resist the assimilation of Wittgenstein into conventional analytic philosophy.

For Bouwsma, Wittgenstein's thought experiments and bizarre juxtapositions represented surrealism, that family resemblance neighbour of magic realism — according to him there were philosophical "realists, critical realists, semi-critical realists and now surrealists" Bouwsma In recent decades the style of scholarship emphasizing "quickening the sense of the queer" has been most widely practiced by the so-called school of "Swansea Wittgensteinians," which formed in the fifties around Wittgenstein's literary executor Rush Rhees, and which has been associated with such names as Peter Winch, D.

Phillips, R. Holland, Ilham Dilman, H. Mounce and Raimond Gaita. As belonging to the same tradition one might also mention Frank Cioffi and his numerous essays on Wittgenstein, anthropology and psychoanalysis, as well as the work done in Finland by Lars Hertzberg on ethics and the philosophy of religion. Mounce and Phillips have built some interesting papers around the observation that we can well understand the meaning of certain propositions without understanding their point.

In a similar way we can only understand certain things preconceptually and prelinguistically without nevertheless sacrificing rationality to intuitions:. The most detailed surveying of Wittgensteinian uncanniness has been done by Gordon Bearn , an American disciple of Cavell and the Swansea school, in his recent book Waking to Wonder: Wittgenstein's Existential Investigations. In Bearn's interpretation Wittgenstein's much-discussed "Kantianism" is reflected interestingly from the way in which Wittgenstein treats concept of the aesthetically and ethically sublime.

In the Critique of Judgement Kant treated as a key problem the question of whether there are experiences that are qualitatively above other experiences Deleuze 46— He also developed the same theme when examining the difference between the beautiful and the sublime. Even though Wittgenstein's conclusions differed from Kant's, his ethical view of life reflects Kantianism; today it is already a platitude to say that Wittgenstein replaced the Kantian limits of reason with the Schopenhauerian limits of language.

As Jonathan Lear ; ; has noted, Wittgenstein brought transcendental idealism "back to Earth" by replacing both the form-content distinction and the idea of a noumenal world with the more simple language-world distinction. According to Lear , his thinking seems to be the same to sociology as Kant's is to empirical psychology. In his interpretation, Bearn takes all of this into account. But he doesn't stop there. When Wittgenstein criticizes logic for wanting to produce qualitatively superior propositions, this mirrors his critique of the similar tendency in ethics.

Wittgenstein takes the theme of the sublime higher than Kant himself; he replaces the lofty Erhaben with the sublime Sublim. In philosophy the idea of the sublime is usually connected with the aesthetics of Kant and Burke, which treats pleasure caused by fear — such as the fear of abysses, chasms and ravines — as superior to ordinary aesthetic experience Lewis ; Bearn 86—87, — Wittgenstein says that the symphonies of Beethoven and Gothic cathedrals are "tremendous things in art"; it is too quantitative, too expert-like to speak of "beauty" in connection with them Wittgenstein 8—9.

It is unholy to do so. Tremendous art sets by itself the criteria with which it is judged tremendous. According to Bearn 86— , Wittgenstein's "sublime" should be understood primarily as a chemical term, only secondarily as an aesthetic one. In philosophy it is thought that logic sublimes, changes directly from the solid to the vapour state. Wittgenstein disapproves of the thought of logic subliming, because he connects the conception of logic he opposes with the critique of "gaseous thoughts" that he presents elsewhere Hilmy — Stern — and of "the queer role which the gaseous and the aethereal play in philosophy" Wittgenstein He also speaks of the "dense mists of language" that surround a philosophical problem Wittgenstein b: When we argue about how meanings can be said to exist, this argument has something occult in it, because the idea of gaseous entities arises so strongly Rotenstreich Logic is sublime because it fears that it would look like magical thinking if it acknowledged its limitations; in fact the magical thinking is in believing that staying silent about them is less harmful than acknowledging them.

Do we think and do we use philosophical concepts because this has turned out to be quite useful? Do we live because it is somehow practical to live? No; we live because we instinctively feel that living is better than not living; " lives are good for you ," as the Liverpool poet Roger McGough puts it. Wittgenstein's magic realism and "quickening the sense of the queer" rescue the familiar concepts of our own form of life by pointing out that they could be otherwise. This is a central way in which the "realistic spirit" of the Diamond—Conant interpretation combats the chimerical "realism" of philosophers with true realism; the unencumbered and sane understanding.

I mean: it is not based on grounds. It is not reasonable or unreasonable. In May Russell wrote to Ottoline Morrell: "I told him he ought not simply to state what he thinks true, but to give arguments for it, but he said arguments spoil its beauty, and that he would feel as if he was dirtying a flower with muddy hands.

His future student Theodore Redpath 16—17 , who had first became acquainted with the Tractatus at the age of sixteen, had formed an image of Wittgenstein as "a kind of prophet I endowed him with the facial appearance of a 'prophet', with a thin long sensitive, El Grecoish kind of face, framed by long strands of silvery hair and set with large, dark, expressive eyes". We can only imagine Redpath's shock when he first met Wittgenstein.

As an example he mentioned the metre of Longfellow's Hiawatha i. Drury Acknowledging the permanence of his overtly compressing tendencies, he said that if it was up to him, the Investigations would be only about a quarter of an inch thick, just like the Tractatus Anscombe It stands there like a natural monument, the result of superlunary dictation. In the eighties an interesting document written by Wittgenstein in January came to light; it suggests that the amount of destroyed material has often been exaggerated, and that the temporal gap in the published notebooks does not necessarily refer to a missing notebook McGuinness According to Stenius, the "picture theory of language" depicted in the Tractatus is preserved in the later philosophy as a limiting case of Wittgenstein's later conception of language.

Stenius quotes a notebook entry from MS , pp. A configuration can be made up by balls which are spatially related in a certain way; but not of the balls and their spatial relations. Lichtenberg on Wittgenstein's thought experiments seems to be clear; often there are almost uncanny similarities between his aphoristic style and Wittgenstein's. It might be fruitful to look at the relationship between the Tractatus and the later Wittgenstein as analogous to the relationship between expressionism and magic realism. It creates new literary forms by voluntarily limiting the exploitation of language.

Bouwsma, who had strongly emphasized the tranquilizing qualities of Wittgenstein: "Well! He electrified us. Whom did he ever tranquilize? Sahlins Wittgenstein would undoubtedly also have opposed this inverse phenomenon. This act, as a sign of piety, is just as understandable as the different one of keeping the scores untouched, accessible to no one. And if Schubert's brother had burned the scores, that too would be understandable as a sign of piety" Wittgenstein a: Even though the various possible signs of piety are mutually contradictory, it is easy to imagine a way of treating the scores which would be a clear sign of lack of piety Clack a: But the existence of interpretations like this proves just how deep the myth of Wittgenstein as a quintessentially analytic philosopher still is is some circles.

Aagaard-Mogensen, L. Haller ed.

ISBN 13: 9781844658534

Ackermann, R. Wittgenstein's City. Amherst, Mass. Anscombe, G. Klibansky ed. Florence: La Nuova Italia: — Bandman, B. Brandl eds. Barnett, W. Barrett, C. Bataille, G. Inner Experience , trans. Albany, N. Bearn, G. Waking to Wonder: Wittgenstein's Existential Investigations. Bouwsma, O. Wittgenstein: Conversations — Indianapolis, Ind. Broyles, J. Burlingame, C. Calhoun, L. Philosophy Unmasked: A Skeptic's Critique.

Lawrence, Kan. Cavell, S. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Cerbone, D. Churchill, J. Basingstoke, Hants. Cioffi, F. Block ed. Oxford: Blackwell: — Clack, B. An Introduction to Wittgenstein's Philosophy of Religion. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press. Conant, J. Putnam, Words and Life.

Cambridge, Mass. Creegan, C. London: Routledge. Cudahy, B. Deleuze, G. London: Athlone Press. It's really his "metaphilosophical" outlook that I find myself constantly recoiling from. That is, it's his views about how to do philosophy and what you can and cannot achieve by doing philosophy that I most firmly reject. Let me explain. Wittgenstein, especially the later Wittgenstein, viewed philosophy as it had been practiced more or less up his own arrival as mostly a budget of confusions.

The rough idea is that a whole lot of philosophy gets going by taking terms like say "knowledge" or "mind" or "idea" or -- take your pick -- and raising questions that have nothing to do with our sort of everyday use of such terms in the context of the "language games" in which they are at home. Take the so-called problem of other minds.

How does this problem get started? Well, Descartes convinced many philosophers that we have immediate and incorrigible access to the contents of our own minds, as if the mind were somehow completely open to itself. It's clear we don't in the same way know the contents of the minds of others. Starting with that observation, it really wouldn't take much argument to get yourself into the frame of thinking that one can reasonably and intelligibly wonder whether we have anyway of knowing about the minds of others.

And once you got yourself into that state of wonder, it wouldn't take a whole lot of further argument to convince yourself to be an utter sceptic about our knowledge of other minds. Of course, at least some other philosophers will be unmoved by your scepticism. They may take themselves to be the guardians of common sense.

But as soon as they admit that your arguments at least deserve answering, that there really is a problem about our knowledge of other minds, then we're off and running on a race to see which set of philosophical arguments will carry the day. Sceptical arguments will war with anti-sceptical arguments. We philosophers tend to think of our problems as "enduring. And Wittgenstein can be seen as offering us an explanation of why we find the problems so intractable. That's the point of his saying that philosophical problems arise when language goes on holiday.

This is not for him a sign that the problems of philosophy are deep. It is rather a sign that they are grounded in utter confusion and abuse of language. Now I won't try to reconstruct the arguments that might lead one down the primrose path of worrying about our knowledge of other minds. I'll leave that as exercise to the reader for now. What Wittgenstein wants to do for philosophy is to give us a way of avoiding taking even the very first step down such paths in the first place. Philosophy should simply stick to describing use. It should abandon the grand hope of building philosophical theories of things like mind, knowledge and self.

It has no particular resources for enabling it to construct such theories in the first place. And all of its past attempts to do so have led to intractable confusion. If we simply look at our actual practices, we will see that the idea that we know the contents of our own minds in some immediate, incorrigible fashion that is different from the way in which we we know the minds of others cannot be sustained.

Full text issues

The very problem that gets the whole intractable debate about our knowledge of self vs. There's something profound about Wittgenstein's approach. Not without reason did generations of later philosophers find it a potent rallying cry. It's certainly true that we want to pay attention to how our language is actually used and we don't want, through mere inattention to the facts of use, to generate pseudo problems. But I have to say that I think it is a serious mistake to think that all the so-called traditional problems of philosophy are mere pseudo-problems borne of insufficient attention to how we actually use certain quite ordinary terms, that, in their everyday use, are completely unproblematic.

Since I'm going to have to leave for the studio pretty soon, I'm not sure I can spell this all out before airtime. Probably I'll come back to it after the show and provide an update. But here's a couple of quick takes on why I don't share Wittgenstein's assessment of the "enduring" philosophical problems and his assessment of what to do about them.

First, I think it's wrong to say that if we just look at how the language is actually used the problem about other minds would simply go away. One needn't doubt that we do know the minds of others. One can simply wonder both how possibly we could know the minds of others and how actually we do, in fact, do so.

Both of these strike me as important and interesting questions. The former is the kind of question that you'll find a philosopher more likely to be asking. I could say a lot about the nature of how possibly questions. Think of what you're doing when you ask and try to answer a how possibly question like this. You've got an initial budget of concepts -- maybe concepts of mind, knowledge, self, others. And reflecting on these concepts you find yourself puzzled as to how these concepts "coordinate" with one another. You can see how possibly a thinking being can know itself, but your puzzled about how a thinking being can know the contents of the mind of another thinking being.

You start to imagine the possibilities. In so doing, you are, as it were, taking an imaginative walk through a range of alternative possible worlds, trying to see if there are any in which one mind knows the contents of another mind. If you find one, and if it's not too far away from the actual world, you conclude that yes one mind can know the contents of another mind. If you don't find one, or if the ones you find are very very far from the actual world, you become a sceptic or conclude that one can only know the contents of one's own mind.

You can read Wittgenstein as arguing that we don't really have any discplined way to walk through the range of possibilities in any way likely to produce stable conviction. Instead of trying to take unconstrained and undisciplined walks through a range of imagined, but un-ordered possibilities, we should just look. Look at how we actually talk about mind, self, knowledge and other in the actual language games we play when we do so in the context of the lived forms of life that give those games point.

I think there is something to this advice. But not everything that Wittgenstein seems to think. Consider the practicing cognitive scientist. What we do when we walk through a range of alternative worlds in the imagination can feel a lot different from what we do when we do science. Take your practicing cognitive scientist who wants to know how minds actually cognize one another.

How does she go about constructing a theory of how people actually manage to know the minds of others. Well one thing she doesn't do is to simply look at how words like "knowledge" "mind" "self" "others" etc are used in ordinary language games. She might take such use as data points.

But she's perfectly prepared to find out that people don't actually have much of a clue as to how we actually go about figuring out what other people think and believe. So what does she do? She deploys more or less tried and true methods of hypothesis generation and testing. She does experiments, she builds models, etc. That is, she draws on all the ways and means of empirical inquiry to try to figure out exactly how, in fact, we so regularly, reliably and systematically figure out what other people feel, believe, and desire.

But what about the poor philosopher? The psychologist cum cognitive scientist in her attempt ot answer the how actually question about our knowledge of other minds is armed to the teeth. She has all the ways and means of empirical inquiry to draw upon. But what do we poor philosophers have to draw on in trying to answer our how possibly question?

Self‐Knowledge: The Wittgensteinian Legacy

One worry might be the one we discussed above. We philosophers really don't have much to draw on except our own unconstrained philosophical imaginations. But philosophical imagination unmoored to the everyday forms of life that give our language games point, is a paltry thing, a thing more likely to mislead than illuminate. So perhaps what Wittgenstein is trying to do by suggesting that we look at how language actually works is simply to give us a way to constrain the imagination in ways that prevent it from just running rampant.

I applaud that instict, if that was the instinct. But take it a step further. Why restrict ourselves to just in tact "language games" in which the problematic terms and concepts supposedly have their homes? You wouldn't recommend that procedure to the practicing psychologist cum cognitive scientist would you? You wouldn't say look only at what people say. Don't do clever experiments designed to ferret out the hidden inner mechanisms or regularities not immediately evident in our everyday practices and our everyday descriptions of those practices.

WHy should the evidential base for our philosophy be more restricted than the evidential base for the construction of psychological and other theories. Because philosophy is, well, different, and sui generis? I don't think so. Philosophy, on my view, is very much continuous with science. I don't mean to say that philosophy is just one science among others. It isn't. For one thing philosophy really is much more concerned, often, with "how possibly, if at all" sorts of questions than the sciences typically are and less concerned with the "how actually" than the sciences typically are.

But how possibly questions should really be thought of as "how possibly, given what we know" questions. And as science increases our knowledge of the actual, we get greater and greater resources for constraining our answers to the how possibly questions that are our stock and trade. Since I'm writing at sort of break-neck pace because I want to get this up before I leave for the studio, I'm not sure if I'm being clear. So let me try a quick statement of a kind of anti-Wittgensteinian bottom line, that concedes something but far from everything to Wittgenstein.

Just starting out bare, with a bare "how possibly question" isn't likely to get you very far. All you have to go on, from square one, is one's own philosophical imagination. But an imagination unconstrained is probably not a reliable guide to anything very deep. Looking at actual language in practice can be one source of constraints. There is a way we actually do talk about the minds of others. There is the actual evidence that we do use to support our actual conclusions about the contents of others minds.

And its wise advice that we start out by looking at such things. But we should also be prepared to look eslewhwere -- at, for example, the deliverances of cognitive science -- and constrain our imaginations by those deliverances as well. And we should also be prepared to find that our everyday practices are sometimes infected with all sorts of illusory material, founded on all sorts of historical mistakes and misdiagnosis that achieve through the mechanisms of cultural transmission the status of received wisdom.

That is, we should be prepared to find that common sense and ordinary usage may themselves stand in need of thoroughgoing reformation. But once we see that we can constrain our imaginations in lots of different ways, from lots of different sources, in its walk through a space of possibilities, why believe that we are prevented from even beginning the walk? Why despair that we will only end in confusion and chaos and intractable fruitless debate? Maybe we will, but we are not bound to. Of course, another worry is that if we make more and more progress on the how actually questions, the how possibly questions will eventually cease to grip us.

And at least that part of philosophy will come to an end. But we are often gripped by how possibly questions when we cannot even begin to get a grip on how the thing actually works. I don't know what mechanisms are actually in there, but let's see what mechanism might be in there. And once we consider which ones might be there, let's see if we can eliminate some of the possible ones and hone in on the actual ones. Is the elimination of possibilites a scientific or a merely philosophical undertaking? I think the answer must be really both and.

And as long as there are domains ripe for conceptual reconfiguration, there will always be room for philosophy. Philosophy will end only when conceptual puzzlement itself comes to an end. Karl Popper Oct 08, Karl Popper is a landmark figure in the philosophy of science. His notion of "falsifiability" endures to this day and even appears in arguments about creation versus evolution. Language in Action Aug 22, How do we communicate ideas with language?

Where does the literal meaning of a word end and the subtle connotation begin? Language and Thought Oct 22, You might think our thoughts simply determine what we say. But maybe the language we speak is what really determines the thoughts we can have. Should We Abandon the Canon? April Philanthropy vs. Are We Slaves to Technology? Is there a Right to Sex? Faith and Humility Happy th, Karl Marx!

Who Gets To Decide the Truth? Dark Knowledge? Is 'The Will of the People' Sacred? Is There a Case for Bullshit? What props up morality? Do Scientists Need Philosophers? Are Americans All Nationalists? Is Neoliberalism Destroying the Earth? Flexitarian vs. Vegetarian Dennett vs. Could the Laws of Physics Change? Could the Laws of Physics Ever Change? How is the Internet Changing Friendships? Transhumanism Cognitive Bias D'oh! Reality TV: Ethics or Entertainment? Can Free Speech Exclude? Should Belief Aim at Truth? Are Taxes Fair? Is This Still the End of History? Is Consciousness an Illusion?

Feel like Democracy is Crumbling? What are Crony Beliefs? Is Postmodernism to Blame for Post-Truth? Why Teach Prisoners? Is it Okay to Punch Nazis? Teaching Philosophy: The Answer to Automation? Introducing: Francis on Film R. April How Many Children? The Culture Wars: Phase 2? Should the ethics of Presidential candidates matter? Nivison The More Good the Better? Why Philosophize? Is Anarchy Possible? Why Be Moral? Does Language Affect Thought? What Might Have Been! What's on your summer reading list for ? What Are Leaders Made of? A blog for Christmas Is it wrong to wreck the earth?

Kierkegaard Is Nothing Sacred Anymore? The Extended Mind What is an adult? Too Much Information? Corporations as Persons Psychological vs. March Fear! Live Blogging! April Journalistic Ethics? Beyond the Cartesian Moment? To blog is to forgive? I tend to have a somewhat deflationary view of why Wittgenstein was so influential. He was one of the few who was really expert at the new logic when it was first becoming a big deal, and at that time there was a perception largely accurate, I think that the new logic was enormously philosophically important and so a tendency on the part of those who didn't quite understand it to be extremely deferential to those who did understand it.

If that is the origin of Wittgenstein's influence, it would explain why his star has fallen so far; mere competence in logic no longer impresses people the way it used to. This is partly because it is more widespread, but also, sadly I think, partly because people have become complacent. Still, while I think the familiarity which has made it harder for modern philosophers to see some of the more dramatic philosophical consequences of post-Fregean logic has produced some retrograde philosophy, I tend to think that to the extent it has undermined Wittgenstein's mystique, that's been a good thing.

Saturday, March 3, -- PM. Not being a Wittengenstein is this just based on the philosopher at the bottom, but at the same time rising toward the middle of the totem pole? To much or too little thinking? One book or books? What makes the great Philosopher stand out in the crowd? What make not being a Wittengenstein a Wittengenstein, a Plato, or even a Socrates? You be the judge. There are many living who profess philosophy.

Not one is a philosopher.

The last living philosopher died in August His mind had been dead since January Like Wittgenstein his native language was German. Who in the 20th or 21st century is fit to untie Nietzsche's bootlaces? Certainly not the misshapen growths suffering from hypertrophy of empirico-logico-linguisticism transplanted into Anglophone seedbeds from decaying and destroyed empires.

Only a Kafka could spin such an absurdist libretto, with bloated score by Mahler. LW is "queer. LW required acolytes. He was oracular. He needs hermeneutics. Surely, Kenneth, there are a few gaps in Wittgenstein's method. But it is useful, anyway. And I would like to comment on some of your ideas using it. You say that philosophy, in contrast to science and anything else , is engaged in questions "how is it possible?

Let us look when such questions arise. You see a trick say, David Copperfield's Laser Illusion and ask "how is it possible to do that? I guess, it is not. We need a trick, anyway. But I think we need something else, as well, to make questions about tricks the philosophical questions: they should be answered by clarification of our concepts only.

I believe, you would agree with that. But are there any tricks which could be solved as a result of clarification of our concepts? I don't know, but if they exist, I doubt we wouldn't able to describe such clarification in terms of Wittgenstein's vocabulary. Indeed, how is it possible: to clarify our concepts? By looking at the use of the terms attached to them, first of all. If it turns out that our concepts are imprecise, why not invent new concepts, new language games? I see no contradictions here with what Wittgenstein had proposed. Monday, March 5, -- PM. It seems like the deflationary view of Wittgenstein's influence, chalking up Wittgenstein's influence just to proficiency with logic, gets things wrong.

The people he influenced early on included Bertrand Russell, Frank Ramsey, and the Vienna circle, which had Carnap and Reichenbach in its ranks. These people were all top notch logicians who wouldn't give someone that much of their time just on the basis of being able to handle logic. Since then Wittgenstein has impressed people like Michael Dummett and Saul Kripke, again great philosophers. I think they saw more in Wittgenstein's thoughts than proficiency with logic. If Wittgenstein's influence is waning, there are probably other sociological or philosophical reasons for it.

It seems like cognitive science is not at odds with being a Wittgensteinian by itself. Other commitments might make one think that Wittgenstein was wrong, but the idea of cognitive science by itself seems compatible. Part of the reason for thinking this is the list of the most influential books in cognitive science published by a group of cognitive scientists from Minnesota.

There are authors on there that are certainly hostile to Wittgenstein, but not all. Hi Shawn: Hope you're enjoying Pitt. A hotbed of at least neo-Wittgensteiniansm I suppose if there ever was one. About Wittgenstein and cognitive science. My point wasn't that cognitive science refutes Wittgenstein. I used cognitive science only to show that "theorizing" about the mind in a way that goes beyond the deliverances of common sense is a perfectly legitimate enterprise.

We do it all the time. And we think we're getting at something deep about the mind when we do. Wittgenstein must think that somehow philosophy isn't entitled to theorize in this way, that when it tries to it's bound to fall into error and confusion. But why think that?

Why think that is any more true of philosophy than of cognitive science? If one thought that philosophy's methods weren't broadly empirical or weren't broadly continuous with empirical methods, you might think something like that. Of course, philosophy isn't exactly science. That was what I meant when I said that philosophy is more likely to be concerned with how possibly questions than science is. But that's not to say philosophy is only concerned with how possibly questions. But the point of comparison was to say that philosophy has at least as many sources of evidence and sources of constraint on its theory construction as science does.

It can, after all, take the entirety of science on board as a source of evidence and constraint. Wednesday, March 7, -- PM. Saturday, March 10, -- PM. Wow, Ken, I found this an incredibly insightful post. It is both generous to Wittgenstein and also probing in its disagreement.

A couple of small points. What you describe--an imagination that is not entirely free, but constrained by science, etc. Also, I think there are two kinds of philosophical "how-possibly" questions. I talk about this distinction in a recent paper of mine, "Molinism", which I can give anyone who is interested. I'll spare you the details here, out of mercy. One kind of question is answered by the contents of a "how-to manual", whereas a deeper as it were kind is answered in a way that may include this sort of content but also engages the most powerful worries of the skeptic about the phenomenon in question.

So, consider time travel. One kind of how-possibly question gets answered in terms of the skeptical worries about the coherence of time travel, the fixity of the past, the direction of causation, the paradox of the power to kill one's grandparents, etc. But another gets answered in terms of a "how-to manual"--first you build the time-machine, etc. Or consider the recent Denzel Washington film, "Deja Vu" for further ruminations on the mechanism of time-travel! I think sometimes even philosophers mix up the two kinds of "how-possibly" questions, settling for an answer suitable to a "how-to manual", where an engagement with skeptical challenges is in order.

Again, let me just say how helpful and insightful I found your post. Monday, April 2, -- PM. I am a bit of a Wittgensteinian, although rather out of practice, having left grad school a few years ago. I would like to offer an answer to the question raised above: why might LW object to philosophical theorizing about the mind, but not to cognitive science? It may be because LW understands philosphy as attempting to deal with necessity and, in his last work, certainty. The philosopher's arguments and theories would concern how things must be, while the scientist's arguments and theories would concern how things in fact happen to be.

Certainly if one looks at the Tractatus, this sort of division between science and philosophy is quite prominent, while in On Certainty it reappears as the distinction between what we know and what is certain for us. Sunday, April 15, -- PM. If Wittgenstein's goal is not yoursif you are correct that his goal is some kind of release from the conundrums of philosophy-- then why should you follow his path?

Still, it is useful to see how he did try to get out from under the sway of philosophical conundrums. But ultimately, if we evaluate his writings from the point of view of his writings--if we apply his own perspective to his own writings--we can see that his problem--that philosophy deals with pseudo- problemsseems itself to be a pseudo-problem. Because certainly ordinary language has no opinion, either way about whether philosophy deals with pseudo-problems or does not. Ordinary language does not seem to agree that his problem is a problem. And certainly Wittgenstein doesn't give us any arguments that ordinary language as a whole has some built-in resistance to being used by philosophers in the way that they do.

If one doesn't share what seems to be his annoyance at being somehow "trapped" by conundrums of a philosophical sort--then I don't see any compelling reason to think his problem any less pseudo than the unnatural philosophical constraints he insists ordinary language is subjected to by others. Surely, he could not deny that he bends ordinary language to his own very philosophical uses within a very philosophical context.

He is not exactly down at the corner store exchanging gossip as he buys tomatoes--right? Tuesday, January 19, -- PM. Ken wrote: "Wittgenstein is for those who can find a resonance in his vision before reading his work" This is a very insightful comment! Saturday, November 24, -- PM.

Site Navigation

I'm a bit frustrated maybe ignorantly with the entry, perhaps five years too late. I think the first objection ludwig would have is that you are using the phrase "mind" like its a word like "apple. We use "mind" to mean something, and removing it from that context reduces it to nonsense. You sublimated the word to a frictionless plane where it's useless or confused. Sure, cognitive scientists can investigate the physical brain and its processes, but that is not an exploration of the "mind," it's an exploration of the brain's physical processes.

The superficial resemblance between the two is clear, but its only a superficial similarity. Monday, July 13, -- PM. Tuesday, April 26, -- PM. Skip to main content. Search form Search. Why I am not a Wittgensteinian. Kenneth Taylor. With that, I really gotta go, as Ian Shoales is found of saying. Related Shows Wittgenstein Mar 04, Hume Mar 01, Karl Popper Oct 08, Karl Popper is a landmark figure in the philosophy of science. Language in Action Aug 22, How do we communicate ideas with language?

Language and Thought Oct 22, You might think our thoughts simply determine what we say. Blog Archive September What's In a Picture? Changing Minds on Climate Change. Against Introspection. A Puzzle About Sacred Values. Self Knowledge on Trial. The Doomsday Doctrine.


  • HR Due Diligence. Mergers and Acquisitions in China.
  • Ludwig Wittgenstein.
  • Site Search Navigation!
  • Judging War Criminals: The Politics of International Justice.

A Simple Test for Fake News. Postmodernism and the Decline of Truth. How to Think Two Thoughts at Once. JS Mill and the Good Life. Letting Go of Human Nature. Tolerance and Radical Disagreement. A Licentious Lannister?

Ludwig Wittgenstein - Wikiquote

Working for Faith. What Is Reading? Anti-Semitism is Racism. FrancisOnFilm: Shazam! Philanthropy vs. Authority and Resistance. Wanting to Want for Its Own Sake. Hacking the Brain. Sexy Beasts. Ken's Big Announcement. FrancisOnFilm: Green Book. Your Question: Integrate or Assimilate? Controversy About Climate Denial. Immigration and Multiculturalism. Mind the Gaps!

Wittgenstein - Ineffability & Limits of Language

FrancisOnFilm: Minding the Gap. Five Types of Climate Change Deniers. Finding Yourself in a Virtual Fiction. FrancisOnFilm: Aquaman. The Puzzle of the Unconscious. Is Envy Always a Vice? FrancisOnFilm: Brexit. Getting Clear on the Replication Crisis. How Not to Fall Asleep. Freud's Philosophical Challenges. December The Examined Year: — Uncut. On Morally Condemning the Past. Philosophical Freud. Foucault on Power. The Creative Life. Does Reputation Matter? Anti-Semitism The Wrong Abortion Question.

How MeToo Helps Men. Can Reason Save Us? The Philosophy of Westworld. Do They Believe in God? The Psychology of Cruelty. Lessons from Lobsters. Athletics and the Philosophical Life.


  1. Well Fed 2: More Paleo Recipes for People Who Love to Eat?
  2. Tertium Organum;
  3. On Ladder Withdrawal Symptoms and One Way of Dealing with Them;
  4. The dynamic Internet: how technology, users, and businesses are transforming the network.
  5. Education and Dramatic Art;
  6. The Ethics of Algorithms. Failing Successfully. FrancisOnFilm: Mission Impossible. Does Science Overreach? The Truly Beautiful Game. Enlightenment Peddlers. Self-Reliance and the Ethics of Homeschooling. One Person, One Vote? Puppet Philosophers. Why America is not a Nation. Distortion in Philosophy.

    Philosophers and the Meaning of Life. The Ethics of Care. Should Robots Be Caregivers? How a Glitch Caused a Crisis. An Antidote to Bullshit. Repugnant Markets. Is Kanye a Philosopher? The Twilight Zone and the Human Condition. What is it Like to Lose Your Identity? Against Marriage. The Morality of Big Business. On Deepities and Bullshit. Consciousness Deniers?

    Faith and Humility. Happy th, Karl Marx! May the Fourth Be With You. Are We Alone? Toppling the Dehumanization Thesis. Are We Really All Equals? Stop Silencing Sex Workers. The Not-So-Goodness of Liberalism? Trolling, Bullying, and Flame Wars. A Case for Conservative Universities. Self Help, Nietzsche, and the Patriarchy. Can Technologies Be Monstrous?

    The End of Privacy. Technology Ethics. The Irreverent Peter Sloterdijk. Is Every Idea Worth Engaging? Adorno and the Culture Industry. From Pessimism to Nihilism. Is Alexa a Setback for Feminism? Racist Algorithms and Fair Sentencing. Humble Disagreement. Philosophy for Prisoners. Moral Philosophy and The Good Place. Stories To Think With. Is Killmonger to Blame?


    • Modern and Past Glacial Environments Revised Student Edition.
    • (PDF) Wittgenstein on grammatical investigations | Talbot J. Taylor - iwuvugiqos.tk.
    • Sidmans Neuroanatomy: A Programmed Learning Tool.
    • Dengue and Dengue Hemorrhagic Fever;
    • Was Wittgenstein Right?.
    • Ludwig Wittgenstein - New World Encyclopedia.
    • Soviet Planning in Peace and War, 1938-1945?

    Is Punishment Wrong? Robot Rights? Misogyny and Gender Inequality. What Makes a Monster? Sexism Versus Misogyny. What Makes a Film Philosophical? The Temptation to Feel Baffled. Is Yoda a Stoic? James Baldwin and Racial Justice. Millennials and Social Media, a Deadly Mix? A Comic Book for 17th-Century Philosophy. FrancisOnFilm: Three Billboards. Fatal Attraction. The Urbanist Delusion. Reasons to Donate to Philosophy. Stranger Feelings. Fanon, Violence, and the Struggle Against Colonialism.

    Is there a real you? Fractured Identities. Do Victims Have Obligations? The Art of Non-Violence. The Puzzle of Possibility. How to Keep Your Resolutions. Thoughts on Retirement. December In Praise of Affirmative Consent. Lethal Speech. An Argument for Regulating Automation. Can Words Kill?

    Buddhism, Science, and the West. Of Philosophy and Basketball. The Midlife Crisis. The Odyssey in Plain English. Scrap Thanksgiving? FrancisOnFilm: Thor Ragnarok. Feminism and Philosophy's Future. Two Models of Hypocrisy. Favorites in Continental Philosophy. The Curious Lives of Octopuses. When Democracy Runs Wild. Basketball: Myths and Puzzles. Achieving a Measure of Insanity. Philosophy of Trash. Compromise and Slavery. Philosophy and Shelley's Frankenstein. Race Matters.

    To Retract or Not to Retract. A Moral Case for Meat. FrancisOnFilm: Battle of the Sexes. Decolonizing Philosophy. The Internet of Things. Harmful Jobs, Net Impact. Frege: The Invisible Anti-Semite. How does Consciousness Happen? On Our Cosmic Insignificance. Getting Rid of "Racism". Should Hate Speech be Protected? The Limits of Free Speech. A World Without Work. How Will Racism Be Eradicated?

    Social Status. Should You Fear AI? Women in Philosophy. Transitions in Philosophy Talk. Credibility and Gender. Are Bosses Like Dictators? Your Question: Changing Physical Laws. The Best of Analytic and Continental Philosophy. Creativity and Character. Which Statues Should Go? Dennett vs. Papineau on Consciousness.